One of my preoccupations is the
difficulty of how the discipline of history – in its modern, quasi-scientific,
secular garb – can engage seriously with profoundly different worldviews. Given
my own interests, I am thinking in particular of how history can deal with the
religious faith of past societies and individuals, and do so without
condescension or dismissiveness. But the point applies more widely. I tried to
address some of these issues in the introduction to my most recent book,
although the best extended consideration of it that I know remains Leigh Eric
Schmidt’s Hearing Things.
So when I see an article in the new American Historical Review,* in which
the ancient historian Greg Anderson argues for an ‘ontological turn’ in which
we take the reality of what he calls other historical ‘lifeworlds’ seriously, I
ought to be delighted. And in many ways I am. I am certainly very stimulated by it (as you can tell). Much of what he says seems like
obviously good sense, especially if, like me, you tend to think that all
history is in the end history of mentalities. And, indeed, if his description
of some of the crudely anachronistic histories of ancient Athens is fair, I am kind
of shocked that respectable scholars are still doing that sort of thing.
So why does the whole thing leave me
feeling a bit queasy?
Anderson is rightly critical of
history-writing which takes what he calls a ‘God’s-eye, “etic” (outsider)’ view of the past,
urging us instead to inhabit those past worldviews. But he does not directly
address the problem which seems to me fundamental here, namely that historians
do not inhabit the past. We inhabit the present. And this is not a liability.
Very good historians can sometimes inhabit both past and present, stretching their
minds to multiple worlds. But the point of doing history is not to inhabit the
past for its own sake, but to understand it from the perspective of the present,
to make it intelligible to the present, and to use all the resources we have
(necessarily, present resources) to interrogate it. Historians are, at best,
the conduits between ages. We need to have a foot in each one.
Failing to recognise that we ourselves are and must be rooted in a
particular historical moment, pretending that we and we alone can transcend our
historical particularity and inhabit other worlds – that seems to me the
ultimate ‘etic’ viewpoint.
Instead, should we not recognise that our present and its knowledge can
bring real value to reading past societies? Take, for example, an event in
ancient Athenian history which Anderson does not mention, the plague of 430
BCE. It seems to me historically sensible to use modern ideas such as germ
theory in order to analyse that event, even though they were not part of the
ancient Athenian ‘lifeworld’. Sometimes we just know stuff they didn’t. And naturally,
they knew stuff that we don’t. The point of a historical conversation with the
past is surely that both we and they are allowed to bring insights to the table.
I am also a little troubled by the sealed, stable ‘lifeworlds’ that he
implies, a bit like native reservations, in which exotic peoples can be admired
in their pristine habitats. It is not simply that modern ideas can sometimes be
powerful analytical tools for examining past societies, but also that past
societies themselves were not stable. I kept expecting Anderson to talk about
my old friends Herodotus and Thucydides, whose views on this particular
question seem to me relevant. Herodotus, famously, used divine agency as an
explanatory tool in his Histories. A
generation later Thucydides, very deliberately, refused to do so. Without
getting into who was right, that suggests that the ancient Athenian ‘lifeworld’
was pretty plural and unstable. Perhaps the truisms Anderson lists – gods,
land, demos and household – were not so universally held. In particular,
perhaps the women, slaves and other voiceless peoples of ancient Athens did not
accept them.
I think Anderson would respond
that this is part of his point: that lifeworlds are contingent and fluid, and
that this extends to our own. But this troubles me too. I mean, he is right, obviously.
But one of the plainest features of this essay is its distaste for modernity.
His description of the modern post-Enlightenment lifeworld – materialist, secular,
anthropocentric and individualist – reeks of disapproval. Fair enough, you
might say, although I am not sure quite which variety of collectivism and supernatural
agency he would like us to adopt instead. But his final line, that an
ontological turn in history may lead us ‘to imagine less exploitative, more
equitable, more sustainable lifeworlds of the future’, gives the game away. That’s
not a historical project, it’s a political one (and is profoundly presentist,
ransacking the past for what it can give us). Historically, studying the past
can reveal to us how deeply contingent, and indeed weird, our own society is: although
I think he overdoes the present’s absolute exceptionalism, a little
narcissistically. Whether that makes us want to critique the present, or,
alternatively, to consider how lucky we all are nowadays, is a political
matter. A perfectly legitimate one, but if you’ve a constructive critique of
modernity to make, let’s have it openly stated, not assumed and framed as
history.
*Greg Anderson, ‘Retrieving the Lost
Worlds of the Past:The Case for an Ontological Turn’ in American Historical Review 120/3 (2015): 787-810.
No comments:
Post a Comment